Monday, December 28, 2015

A Skeptical Response to the "Good Guys with Guns" Argument

Whenever a mass shooting occurs, gun-rights advocates say that if only there had been an armed civilian present, the shooter could have been taken down. Gun advocates point to cases in which an armed bystander has taken out a shooter. But this is not the only way for society to deal with gun violence, and especially in mass shootings, this response is very risky to the armed civilian and everyone else. Many of these mass shootings involve high-powered weapons that fire bullets rapidly. When a shooter comes into a school, a mall, an office building, or wherever, and starts spraying bullets, what is a person going to do—pull out their own AR-15 and start spraying bullets back? Suppose there are ten people present with their own assault rifles, firing from all directions. Is this going to prevent more people from being killed, or is it mainly going to cause collateral damage?

Perhaps assault rifles are too cumbersome for your average "good guy" to want to carry around everywhere, so people carry concealed handguns instead. Imagine that a killer comes in and starts rapid-fire shooting. A bystander pulls out a handgun and aims at the shooter. How likely is it that the person is going to actually hit the shooter? Especially in the frantic state the bystander is likely to be in, this armed civilian is going to have to be a virtually perfect shot. Otherwise he is likely to miss the shooter while drawing the shooter’s attention (and a barrage of bullets) to himself, or, of course, to accidentally hit another person. In this situation, it seems more natural for a person to get down and hide than to stand and face a barrage of bullets, which would seem at least as likely to result in the bystander getting hit with the killer’s many bullets as for the person to hit the shooter with one or two of his own.

My point is not that it is impossible to reduce the body count in a mass shooting this way; in some cases, this has happened. But as a model for the proper response to gun violence, this approach seems extremely risky at best, and just as likely to result in more death as to take out the killer.

The gun advocates will say, "What would you rather people do, stand there defenseless while people are being killed?" I believe that their preferred alternative is likely to result in more deaths than hiding and waiting for the arrival of professionals trained for this kind of situation, but gun-rights advocates will never agree with that. But perhaps a majority of citizens will be open to an alternative policy that will make such attacks less likely to occur in the first place, and thus save people from having to confront a person who is armed with a weapon of war. The proper policy is to restrict access to assault weapons in order to make it more difficult for would-be shooters to acquire them in the first place.

Of course, gun advocates purport to believe that gun control laws are useless in preventing violence, because criminals don’t follow laws. If we take that blanket proposition seriously, we of course have no basis for restricting any weapon, including automatic weapons, rockets, grenades, and other military weapons. After all, if people were really determined, they could get hold of such weapons regardless of the law. But the fact that criminals don’t follow laws does not, as gun advocates assume, mean that killers are not hindered by laws. Well-enforced laws can indeed make a criminal’s plans harder to carry out.

Therefore, if we could make access to these weapons even a little bit harder, we could prevent some mass shooting deaths. A killer might have to resort to a less powerful weapon, and kill ten people instead of 20. Many mass shooters purchase their weapons legally; they are not career criminals with access to a steady supply of illegal weapons from which gun control laws would not keep them. Adam Lanza got many of his weapons from his mother’s collection. If such weapons had not been legal, there is a good chance that those weapons would not have been in that house, and Lanza might either not have done the shooting or would have had to find some other source for weapons; perhaps he would have ended up with less-powerful weapons, and killed five or ten people instead of 26.

Of course, it’s true that no law, however well-enforced, will prevent all gun deaths. But well-enforced laws can prevent some deaths. Which is why, despite the fact that criminals don’t follow laws, we still attempt to restrict criminals’ access to guns—because even if we can’t ensure that no criminal gets a gun, we can at least make it more difficult for them to do so, and that is well worth it.
It is sad and unnecessary that Americans have to face the dilemma of whether to hide and wait for the police or to take out guns and start firing. In most other advanced democracies, people do not confront this choice. Australia has not had a mass shooting since the country enacted strict gun legislation in 1996; in the same span of time before the legislation, there were 112 mass shootings.


Nor is the success of the nation's gun legislation limited to mass shootings. Margaret Hartmann writes: "…In 2012 a study by Australian National University's Andrew Leigh and Wilfrid Laurier University's Christine Neill concluded that in the decade after the law was introduced, the firearm homicide rate dropped by 59 percent and the firearm suicide rate fell by 65, with no corresponding increase in homicides and suicides committed without guns." (Source: http://nymag.com/daily/intelligencer/2015/10/how-australia-and-britain-tackled-gun-violence.html ) The likelihood that this legislation contributed nothing to this decline in gun violence seems very small.

The U.K. also enacted restrictive gun laws after the Dunblane massacre, also in 1996. It is difficult to tell how much difference that law made in the frequency of mass killings, since the country had so few anyway, and the overall gun crime rate did not change much, again probably because it had so little gun crime to begin with. The country simply does not have nearly as many guns as we do, leading to the startling conclusion that, in the absence of guns, gun deaths are quite rare.


Of course, the absence of guns would be nearly impossible to achieve in the United States. We enacted an assault weapons ban in 1994, but the ban was allowed to expire in 2004; gun-rights absolutism grew in popularity and political power in the intervening years. Even if we managed to re-enact the ban on assault weapons, there would still be many such firearms in civilian hands, as confiscation of existing weapons (as took place in the U.K.) would be unthinkable here. It would probably still be more difficult for a would-be killer to obtain such a weapon, if one could not be easily acquired legally. Yet most gun violence would be unaffected by such a ban, as most gun deaths involve handguns. If a ban on assault weapons would be exceedingly difficult to pass, a ban on handguns would be virtually impossible.

So it is a depressing fact that Americans will continue to face armed killers much more often than people in other countries like ours. If I were ever in that situation, I would surely root for the brave person who took out a weapon and fired back at the assailant. But it’s a shame that we have to settle for this when, with sensible gun laws, we could prevent this from being necessary.  

Saturday, December 19, 2015

A Defense of Redistribution (and Critique of Ayn Rand's Popular Ideology)

At times I doubt that it is worthwhile to refute arguments made by people of the Ayn Rand ilk, in part because the ideology’s many sympathizers seem impervious to any challenge to their myopic worldview, and in part because the existence, if not the adequate funding, of the welfare state does not appear to be in any immediate jeopardy. Yet Randian views are fairly prevalent on the right, even if right-libertarians' radically anti-statist goals remain forever beyond their reach. We still have a relatively democratic form of government, which responds to popular demands for a modicum of security and opportunity for people born, or thrown, into poverty. For any government, including a Republican-led one, to radically upend this system would be to incur certain electoral defeat.

Yet I find myself irresistibly drawn to the discussion about this peculiar ideology. A prominent right-libertarian author of the 20th century, Ayn Rand saw selfishness as a virtue that was mistaken for a vice. She was countering those who believed that sacrificing one’s own interests for the sake of someone else’s was a moral good. For Rand, this was perverse. People of great talent and strong work ethic, Rand believed, had become far too selfless. People would be far better off if they sought great wealth unencumbered by concerns about the less fortunate.

I went through an Ayn Rand phase when I was 19, reading “The Fountainhead”, “Atlas Shrugged”, and “The Virtue of Selfishness” with considerable, if fleeting, respect. Since an aggressive and winner-take-all form of capitalism seemed victorious, I welcomed a reason to believe in such a system and feel vindicated rather than hopelessly defeated. Yet never once in my life had I found myself thinking, “You know what the problem with the world is? People are thinking too much of others, and not enough about their own interests.” Nor did Rand's work convince me to entertain such a thought. Such a proposition seemed quite readily debunked by simple observation of most people’s behavior.

To me, at least, it seems pretty clear that most people take care of themselves and their families first, and then, if they are so inclined, give a fraction of whatever is left over to others. Just look at the way people accumulate huge amounts of wealth and use it for their own benefit. They pay taxes on that wealth, of course, but often grudgingly and using whatever means they can to shield as much from the government as possible. Affluent people often send their children to colleges costing $50,000 per year or more; if they were really as self-sacrificing as they are accused of being, they presumably would send their children to perfectly acceptable state universities and donate the saved money to support college education for poorer young people. (And if this did happen, it would be a horror that I suspect we could learn to live with, Rand's objections notwithstanding.)

I do not blame people for wanting to keep their money when they move from poverty to the middle class, nor do I fault the middle class for wanting to maintain and improve their lot. Lacking the comprehensive social welfare state of most other advanced democracies, Americans have to accumulate a large amount of private wealth to achieve economic security. The last few years of life, if lived in serious illness, can easily wipe out a lifetime of savings and investments. This might help the case for a more comprehensive welfare state, but just as it seems unlikely that America will abolish the limited social welfare system that it has, it seems equally unlikely that the country will adopt the cradle-to-grave Scandinavian model.

Yet, since there are many who think otherwise, I feel driven to defend the welfare state. Earlier, I called the Randians' belief system peculiar; the reason is that the system mistakes a phantom of absolute social equality for the real thing, and its devotees are not placated in the least when the misperception is pointed out to them, even with undeniable evidence. A recent social media post, paraphrasing a common conservative assertion, declared that “Effort and talent are unequal, so it would be unfair for income to be equal.” If you believe that there is any danger of everyone’s income being equal, you must believe that the proposed $15-per-hour minimum wage would make workers’ pay equal to that of executives. If so, I would encourage you to do some research into executive pay. Even Bernie Sanders would never allow absolute equality, for then he would be a communist and not a democratic socialist. Nor does progressive taxation seek to establish total equality, since even with high rates, it still takes only a fraction of people's wealth as they become richer. Those who would tax 100% of people's income past a certain point do exist on the left, but they are mostly confined to narrow academic circles and marginal political organizations. Given the great increase in income inequality in the past few decades, which has been more or less maintained during seven years under a liberal Democratic president, the fear of absolute economic equality does not seem particularly well-founded. Just as there are democratic pressures maintaining support programs for low-income people, there are pressures against dramatic increases in taxes on richer people. They, too, donate, lobby, and vote; indeed, richer people vote more consistently than poorer people do.

The result is that a 4.6% increase in tax on income exceeding $250,000 was a hard-won achievement for progressives; presumably, a more aggressively confiscatory tax policy would be harder to pass through Congress. The alleged malign selflessness has not prevented legislators from taxing capital gains more lightly than ordinary income, maintaining the carried-interest loophole, or substantially eliminating the inheritance tax, all policies that reflect the considerable political power of very affluent people quite unashamedly looking after their own interests. Nor does it prevent state legislatures from levying a cornucopia of taxes and fees that take a larger fraction of poorer people’s income than richer people’s. When I paid nearly $200 for a vehicle registration fee, I would have welcomed some selflessness on the part of the people--most of whom enjoy an income much greater than mine--who determine the fees. 

To be clear, I do not completely oppose conservative economic policy. For example, there is a reasonable case for lower capital-gains taxes, given the existence of corporate income tax. A too-large state can encumber economic growth; free markets produce more wealth and overall economic well-being than central planning. But the discussion here focuses on putative evidence for radical self-sacrifice among successful people, Ayn Rand’s heroes, and that evidence is thin. A substantial decrease in the size of economic inequality might make a transition to an egalitarian dystopia at least a remote possibility, but since that is plainly not happening, radical anti-redistributionist rhetoric seems to be a straw-man attack.

In fairness, right-libertarians do have a plausible argument to make even if they concede that absolute equality is not being proposed. According to those in this group, any redistribution is morally equivalent to robbing people at gunpoint. This makes discussion of precise amounts and uses of redistribution irrelevant, since robbery is wrong whether you take $5 or $5,000, and whether you give it to a homeless person or use it to gamble at the race track. But this objection to social welfare reflects a distorted view of socioeconomic reality. People on the far left, of course, have their own naïve economic beliefs, but right-libertarians are taken with the belief that heavily concentrated wealth does not buy its owners political power and the distribution of rewards and privileges that inevitably follows from it. A plentiful supply of labor enables an employer to dictate the terms of employment to a worker, a significant advantage to the employer that can force the worker to either accept poor working conditions at one job or accept similar conditions at another. This is not physical coercion, of course, but it is an exercise of power over a person that warrants some kind of mitigation, even if only meaningful collective bargaining rights. You can imagine what would happen if, in addition to this advantage, successful people also did not have to pay for poor people to receive food and housing assistance, health care, or education. (Recall, all of these things are paid for by ostensibly robbing the rich.) The assurance of education is what enables many to have choices beyond those indicated in my example. If such assistance were not provided at taxpayer expense, many, if not most, poor people would stay poor no matter what they did. If this is the kind of society you prefer, that is your right, but do not pretend that such a society is free for people without resources.

Nor is my example the only way in which richer people can effectively take wealth from poorer people. Read Steven Teles’s “Kludgeocracy in America” to become educated on the ways in which some wealthier people game the system to enrich themselves at the expense of poorer people. Unlike Teles, I think the most practical solution is to use downward redistribution to compensate for the upward kind, but whether you agree or not, after becoming more aware of planned distortions in a supposedly laissez-faire system, you will see that the notion that existing economic inequality largely reflects the function of the free market becomes insupportable.

Perhaps the solution is to remove these distortions and allow the free market to work its magic unfettered. Strong right-libertarians go even farther than this. Perhaps you are inclined to agree with them that redistribution equates to robbery. If so, you probably implicitly share certain suppositions with the Randians that liberals and even some conservatives do not. One of the main suppositions is that people are largely autonomous and independent, entering and withdrawing from society as they find necessary and expedient. As such, people can pick and choose what social programs they would like to support. Of course, there are certain items, such as law enforcement, national defense, and the justice system, that people necessarily must support, since they benefit from these services whether they like it or not, and, if funding these services were voluntary, some would choose to free-ride off of those who agreed to pay. Libertarians are not necessarily anarchists; even Ayn Rand agreed that taxation was necessary. But according to this philosophy, people’s dependence on society is very limited and does not extend to social welfare. Misfortune might render me desperately poor someday, but, if I so wish, I could choose not to support social welfare programs, making myself ineligible for benefits, if the law so allowed; I could save my money and take my chances.

In theory, the government could abolish social welfare programs altogether or make their funding voluntary. In order to prevent people from opting not to pay but collecting benefits later, people who declined to support the system could be made ineligible for benefits. Of course, this would cause some serious problems. Some, presumably, would opt not to pay, and thus greatly reduce the funding available for people in need, and, as misfortune rendered some non-payers desperately poor, we would have a growing number of extremely poor people facing starvation, homelessness, and disease. They could seek charity, of course, but presumably there would be a limit to how much support philanthropic people and institutions would be able to provide for a growing number of desperate people. 

It has been said to me in response to this line of argument that people should suffer the consequences of their choices, and that, seeing others suffer and die as a result of their foolishness, people would make more responsible choices. Seeing the state protect people against the consequences of their actions, the argument goes, people are encouraged to make irresponsible choices and then get to force others to pay the price. The argument against redistribution in principle thus has a utilitarian bonus to add to its deontological basis.

This argument has problems of its own. People can become desperately poor for reasons having nothing to do with irresponsible personal choices. But in any case, none of the disastrous consequences of the abolition of the welfare state would pose a problem for those opposed to redistribution in principle. If taxing people to support the poor is fundamentally morally wrong, it does not matter what the consequences of declining to do so would be. Property rights are sacrosanct, and, presumably, people can only be forced to support the basic functions of government listed above.

Yet, properly understood, social welfare is one of these basic, necessary government functions. Unfortunately, and perhaps to the discredit of its defenders, social welfare is not properly understood. Social welfare is portrayed, sometimes even by its defenders, as a one-way obligation of a richer person to a poorer one. This makes social welfare vulnerable to the argument that people are not entitled to other people’s property.

Cass Sunstein has a blunt way around this problem. To the taxpayer, he says, “It’s NOT your money.” By law, whether we like it or not, some of our money belongs to the government; we can vote for legislators who make that quantity greater or less, depending on our preferences, but once that decision is made, we cannot rightfully decide that money owed in tax is our own. Unless we agree to this, government itself becomes impractical if not impossible, since people will naturally want the benefits of government without the cost. While Sunstein is right that the money we owe in tax is by definition not our own, this point is unsatisfactory, on its own, as a justification for social welfare spending. Just because the government can do something does not mean that it should do so.

To be sure, it is entirely right for the government to help those who cannot help themselves; those who disagree in principle are deeply misguided, as I will attempt to show. But the “It’s not your money” argument is not enough to show why this is so. That is, there is no individualistic way to justify redistribution. Once it is conceded (wrongly) that people thrive largely independently of others—that is, that it is possible for people to separate their own welfare from that of others—the case for redistribution is weakened, perhaps fatally so. Fortunately for those who support redistribution, this proposition is absurd. The individual cannot thrive without society; therefore, the argument that the individual should not have to pay taxes to support the welfare of other people is indefensible. The individual is not supporting other people to his own detriment (as would be true in the case of actual robbery); he is paying to sustain a community upon which he depends--that is, to support the social system without which the wealth he claims for himself could not have been acquired in the first place. 

You might object, “How does my welfare depend on the provision of material aid to people able to support themselves who choose instead to collect benefits? I just saw a person pay for prime rib with food stamps!” I might agree that people blowing their $3 per day on fancy food early in the month is a political issue of great concern, but you must agree that at least some government assistance goes to people in genuine need. (If not, I have some people I would like you to meet.) In any case, you cannot very well divert a deontological argument in a utilitarian direction when you find that the argument is failing; if you oppose mandatory social insurance in principle, you oppose it whether its beneficiaries are deserving or not. And I am not asking you to concede that all social welfare spending is to your own advantage; I am as painfully aware as you are that a substantial amount of government spending serves the selfish interests of politically connected constituencies. But I do not see how you can get by in life without benefitting from the services of people who became productive members of society because the government provided for them. Meet your author, who suffers from a debilitating illness but is able to contribute to society because the government pays for much of his health care. (Thanks, by the way. And you’re welcome.)

You might object, “But you get your wages!” Yes, but not nearly enough to pay for the medical care I need in order to be able to earn those wages. So the government makes up the difference, for me and for others in similar circumstances, and everyone more or less benefits. You necessarily depend on me, and I necessarily depend on you.

Perhaps this argument is academic, since even legislators on the right are not proposing to eliminate all social welfare spending. But ideological discomfort with redistribution is often exploited to resist expansions in our social support system, and motivates the push for cuts to that system. (See the proposal to eliminate Obamacare, and I do not share the confidence of many on the right that, should its opponents succeed, they will replace the law with one providing similar benefits to the most vulnerable people.) So it is important that people understand why government support for the vulnerable is necessary and legitimate.

Even though radical right-libertarianism is flawed, it is difficult to challenge, since its individualistic assumptions are so deeply rooted in our culture that any discussion of social policy, even in defense of social welfare spending, tends to rely on individualistic language and make individualistic arguments. So if redistribution is to be properly supported, it must be supported in communitarian rather than individualistic terms. This is not easy to do in a culture that so fanatically devoted to individual rights that it sees even basic positive social obligations as an affront to liberty. To change this distorted view, welfare supporters must reconceive the individual as part of a larger social organism, no part of which can thrive without the adequate care of the other parts. That is, Rand is wrong. Society is more than the sum of its parts; those parts do not function interdependently only as they see fit on a case-by-case basis, and withdraw whenever they become exhausted and shrug. Is this socialistic? Absolutely. You are a member of a society; it depends on you, and you depend on it. Embrace it, Comrade!

“But what about the malingerers?” What about them? According to my argument, we are all, at some level, necessarily and inescapably dependent on one another and the social organism of which we are a part, and yet no organism is perfectly healthy. We have ailments; we might even have vestigial parts, which do nothing for society’s benefit but do depend on society for their survival. Of course, as a matter of good social policy, we might treat the ailment; we might well decide that these folks are indeed draining scarce resources from people who desperately need them; we might decide that some tough love is in order for them, and to their benefit; and provided that decent-paying employment is available for such folks, I am inclined to agree with these assertions. But I am refuting the objection to social welfare in principle, not social welfare in admittedly imperfect practice, since the objection in principle is the one being uncritically echoed by Rand’s free-thinking, fiercely independent fans.

I do not pretend to have an elegant solution to every problem, nor an airtight argument for every position I take. Like others, I often look for arguments to support positions suggested by my intuitions, and this is hardly a perfect science. If you do not agree with my communitarian defense of social welfare, I hope that you will find your own reasons to support at least a safety net for the poor. But I do encourage people to look critically at the arguments made by those who interpret moderate redistribution as evidence of creeping totalitarianism. Decades into America’s experiment with the welfare state, we are in many ways, despite dire warnings, freer and more prosperous than ever before. And we have a mild form of democratic socialism to thank for it.

(1) Teles, http://www.nationalaffairs.com/publications/detail/kludgeocracy-in-america
(2)Sunstein, http://home.uchicago.edu/~csunstei/celebrate.html

Sunday, October 11, 2015

Criminals Don't Follow Laws. Pass Them Anyway.

Because not everyone who commits a gun murder is previously a criminal


I have heard many people make the assertion that gun control laws are useless because “criminals don’t follow laws.” I have heard this argument many times over the years, but lately I have been hearing it constantly—perhaps because we didn’t have Twitter when the Columbine massacre happened, but today when a mass shooting occurs, which is often, we now have a way to vent our simplistic views on the subject in a 24/7 forum.


I have been holding my tongue when I hear the “criminals don’t follow laws” argument. Not because I am afraid of people disagreeing with me. I actually enjoy exchanging different views, and people have every right to express theirs, no matter how extreme or ill-considered. But I suppressed my response because I figured that there was no use in saying anything; people have made up their minds and no amount of argument, no matter how rational and logical, would convince die-hards on either side.


But not everyone is a die-hard. Some people are open-minded enough to consider reasonable arguments and adapt (if not wholly change) their views to accommodate them. So here is my best try.


For one thing, the assertion that we should not enact gun laws because criminals don’t follow them must be an exaggeration. If people really thought that gun laws were completely useless in preventing gun violence, there would be no reason for them to support background checks. After all, a determined criminal will always be able to get a gun, so we need not bother with mandatory background checks. For that matter, all military weapons should be legal for civilian possession—machine guns, rockets, grenades. After all, criminals will always be able to get them, and law-abiding people might need to defend themselves.


Of course, this would be an absurd argument, as even pro-gun people must admit that background checks at least make it more difficult for a person with a criminal record to get a gun. It is also true that many pro-gun people are against background checks for private sales and gun shows, but at least in principle, they support the policy of not allowing guns to be sold to criminals. Moreover, pro-gun people are not saying that all military-type weapons should be legal for civilians to own. They understand in principle that at least some laws can be enforced and can be effective. So even according to gun enthusiasts, it cannot be true that gun laws are completely useless.


But if you concede that certain laws can help prevent gun violence, you must abandon glib statements and address the merits of proposed laws on a case-by-case basis.


But isn’t it true that since criminals ignore laws, gun control will only disarm law-abiding people?


No.


In most of the mass shootings that have occurred in the past several years, the killers acquired their weapons legally. And why wouldn’t they? Most of them did not have a criminal record that would have precluded a legal gun purchase. An alienated, disturbed person with violent fantasies but no criminal record can walk into a gun store and walk out with a weapon that fires bullets rapidly. If the law did not allow such a weapon to be sold, the person would at least have to go to greater lengths to obtain the weapon. Perhaps he wouldn’t be able to locate a source for one.  


So it is simply not true that guns used in violent crimes are always illegal guns and thus beyond the reach of gun laws. Many of these guns start out as legal ones, and then they either fall into the wrong hands, or a previously law-abiding person turns violent. That is, having permissive gun laws makes killing easier. More restrictive laws would not make killing impossible, of course—just more difficult. Why shouldn’t we at least do that? If we could have saved even a small number of gun violence victims, would that not have been worth it? If the next Adam Lanza could not easily obtain an AR-15 and instead had to resort to a less powerful weapon, and the killer could murder only 15 people instead of 26, would a stricter gun law not be worth it?


But people need these weapons to defend themselves!


No, they don’t. Suppose a killer walks into a crowded public place and starts firing. For one thing, for the reasons I already said, well-enforced restrictive laws might prevent that from even happening—or he might at least come in with a less-powerful weapon. But even supposing he can still lay his hands on a rapid-firing weapon, what do you suppose the bystanders are going to do? Take their assault rifles off their shoulders and start firing back? Great—now you have a war going on in a dark movie theater—a shopping mall—an elementary school—or a community college. You suppose there won’t be collateral damage from the spraying of bullets in all directions?  


One of the law-abiding civilian soldiers might eventually strike down the killer, and that might be reason enough to allow people to carry around weapons designed for war. But it’s a war that should not be necessary. It’s a war that they don’t have to fight in Australia, which enacted strict gun control in 1996 and has not had a mass shooting since, despite having 112 mass shooting deaths in the same span of time before the legislation. There is no need for people to carry around military weapons if the law keeps society safe. And yes, the law can help keep society safe—by making the most lethal weapons harder to get. And yes, strict gun control makes guns harder to get, even for people who mean to do violence.


Granted, perhaps that assertion is not true for career criminals. Perhaps for people in organized crime or in gangs, it would be just as easy to obtain guns if the laws were restrictive. But not every person who commits a violent gun crime is a career criminal with easy access to weapons. Some are previously law-abiding people who decide for whatever reason to kill innocent people. And we won’t even attempt to make it more difficult for them to get the weapons they need to do it.    


Evidence from Australia supports my argument. Margaret Hartmann writes: “…In 2012 a study by Australian National University's Andrew Leigh and Wilfrid Laurier University's Christine Neill concluded that in the decade after the law was introduced, the firearm homicide rate dropped by 59 percent and the firearm suicide rate fell by 65, with no corresponding increase in homicides and suicides committed without guns.” (Source: http://nymag.com/daily/intelligencer/2015/10/how-australia-and-britain-tackled-gun-violence.html )


Another important point is that the assertion “Guns don’t kill people” is also wrong. True, a person pulls the trigger, and the person is responsible for the act. But once the person pulls the trigger, the gun does the rest of the work. The gun fires the bullet, the bullet tears through the flesh and punctures a vital organ and, yes, kills the victim. So if you take away the gun, in some cases, the killing won’t happen. A fist or a club or a knife might not do it. A headline in 2012 read: “Knife attack at Chinese school wounds 22 children” (Source: http://www.cnn.com/2012/12/14/world/asia/china-knife-attack/). Had the weapon been a gun, “wounds” would surely be “kills” for at least some of those children.


If you are willing to take that risk for the sake of an extreme notion of constitutional liberty, you have every right to feel that way. But at least admit that the cost of this position is to make killing easier and more frequent.

Saturday, July 25, 2015

The Controversy over "Black Lives Matter": A Big (and Typical) Misunderstanding


"Black Lives Matter" really means "Black Lives Matter, Too"

When Martin O’Malley said, “Black lives matter, white lives matter, all lives matter”, a great backlash resulted. The backlash came from people who emphasize that “Black lives matter” and have turned the assertion into a slogan. Of course, O’Malley’s statement in and of itself is perfectly valid, but the statement in and of itself is not being disputed. What is being disputed is the false equivalence implied by the statement.

People who say “Black lives matter” are working from a certain premise. Their premise could be right or wrong, but before their position is attacked, that premise ought to be understood. The indignant response to the criticism of those who retort “All lives matter” shows serious misunderstanding of the issue.

Perhaps there are people who believe that black lives matter more than white ones or other ones. But for most of those saying “Black lives matter”, their motivating belief is that black lives have been, and remain, particularly undervalued in our society. That’s what I’m calling their premise. 

It should not be controversial to say that historically, black people have been valued less and treated particularly badly, or at least, valued less and treated worse than whites. There is legitimate debate over how much this injustice has been corrected, and how much of the disparity remains. But people should not be faulted for thinking that some anti-black discrimination—official, structural, or otherwise—remains. And when they say in response to the killing of a black person by a police officer that “Black lives matter”, their protest should be understood for what it is—a protest against the undervaluing of black lives, not a claim that other lives don’t matter.

Since the claim that non-black lives don’t matter is not (generally) being made, therefore, the retort that “All lives matter” is beside the point. Of course all lives matter, but when that statement is made in this context, it suggests that the particularly discriminatory treatment of blacks historically and to some extent presently is not a fact.

So even if you do not agree that black lives remain undervalued compared to white lives, you should at least understand where those emphasizing the value of black lives are coming from. To emphasize the value of a persecuted group is not to deny the value of other groups, but to emphasize the value of other groups in response is to deny (or at least minimize) the undervaluing of the persecuted group. So "Black Lives Matter" really means "Black Lives Matter As Much, So Please Treat Them Accordingly". Maybe not as pithy a slogan, but thoughtful people should be able to infer the left-out part.